"hyperphenomenal" meaning in English

See hyperphenomenal in All languages combined, or Wiktionary

Adjective

IPA: /ˈhaɪ.pə(ɹ)ˌfəˈnɒmɪnənəl/ [Received-Pronunciation], /ˈhaɪ.pə(ɹ)ˌfəˈnɑməˌnɑnəl/ [General-American] Forms: more hyperphenomenal [comparative], most hyperphenomenal [superlative]
Etymology: hyper- + phenomenal Etymology templates: {{prefix|en|hyper|phenomenal}} hyper- + phenomenal Head templates: {{en-adj}} hyperphenomenal (comparative more hyperphenomenal, superlative most hyperphenomenal)
  1. (rare) Above and beyond what is phenomenal; superphenomenal. Tags: rare
    Sense id: en-hyperphenomenal-en-adj-6yRhwJPO Categories (other): English entries with incorrect language header, English terms prefixed with hyper-

Download JSON data for hyperphenomenal meaning in English (6.3kB)

{
  "etymology_templates": [
    {
      "args": {
        "1": "en",
        "2": "hyper",
        "3": "phenomenal"
      },
      "expansion": "hyper- + phenomenal",
      "name": "prefix"
    }
  ],
  "etymology_text": "hyper- + phenomenal",
  "forms": [
    {
      "form": "more hyperphenomenal",
      "tags": [
        "comparative"
      ]
    },
    {
      "form": "most hyperphenomenal",
      "tags": [
        "superlative"
      ]
    }
  ],
  "head_templates": [
    {
      "args": {},
      "expansion": "hyperphenomenal (comparative more hyperphenomenal, superlative most hyperphenomenal)",
      "name": "en-adj"
    }
  ],
  "hyphenation": [
    "hy‧per‧phe‧nom‧en‧al"
  ],
  "lang": "English",
  "lang_code": "en",
  "pos": "adj",
  "senses": [
    {
      "categories": [
        {
          "kind": "other",
          "name": "English entries with incorrect language header",
          "parents": [
            "Entries with incorrect language header",
            "Entry maintenance"
          ],
          "source": "w"
        },
        {
          "kind": "other",
          "name": "English terms prefixed with hyper-",
          "parents": [],
          "source": "w"
        }
      ],
      "examples": [
        {
          "ref": "1882, Adam and Charles Black, Edinburgh, Encyclopedia Britannica & Dictionary - Ninth Edition (25 Volumes), Boston Book Company, page 8",
          "text": "In this sense we can say that all positive law—that is, all law exis ing in fact—is “natural”; by examining its determining factors and conditions we may come to understand its relative necessity and, as we say, explain it historically, but this does not imply any judgment concerning its intrinsic value as measured by the ideal standard of justice. This ideal is defined by the supreme law which corresponds to the spiritual essence of man, that is, to his hyperphenomenal nature. It is only in this latter sense that we can properly speak of natural law, as a paradigm and a rational criterion standing above positive law and enabling us to judge its value.",
          "type": "quotation"
        },
        {
          "ref": "1891, George Berkeley, Alexander Campbell Fraser, Selections from Berkeley: With an Introduction and Notes for the Use of Students in the Universities, page 37",
          "text": "He afterwards (§§ 3-24) goes on to argue that there can be nothing hyperphenomenal, or independent of a percipient mind, in the things of sense at least,—consistently with that faithful acceptance of experience, and rejection of empty words, on which he insists in the preceding Introduction.",
          "type": "quotation"
        },
        {
          "ref": "1897, Francis Turner Palgrave, Landscape in Poetry from Homer to Tennyson, Macmillan and Company, Limited, page 5",
          "text": "Compared with Nature in her infinite vastness, her infinite minuteness, our sphere is indeed limited. It is the surface of this little world—or, indeed only a small part of that surface—with sky and its earthbom features, and beyond, the heavenly bodies, as the fine old phrase names them, with which we are concerned; yet the aspects of Nature to man as he sees and loves and strives to render them in poetry, from the beginning we shall find have constantly either expressed or implied the sense of Divine causation or presence; and with this, that mysterious sense that we also are in some way one with what we see; that silent voices are speaking to us from land and sky, even that whatever we find of real existence, of the hyperphenomenal (if I may use the word) in ourselves, is immanent throughout the Cosmos. Or (to quote from an eminently thoughtful writer) man's personifications of natural scenery, we may say, are\" not the result of any mere ignorant \"fancy by which we project ourselves into external Nature, but \"evidently the result of an instinctive recognition of that\" special kind of agency which is, indeed, familiarly known to \"us as existing within ourselves, but which is also universally\" recognised and identified as existing outside of us and around \"us, on every side. It is a reflection of that infinite Reason,\" that Logos — of which we partake, and without which in \"Nature was not anything made that was made. All things, \"including ourselves, are full of it.\"",
          "type": "quotation"
        },
        {
          "ref": "1901, John James Tigert, Theism: A Survey of the Paths That Lead to God, Chiefly in the Light of History of Philosophy, Publishing House of the M.E. Church, South, Barbee & Smith, page 319",
          "text": "Mind you it is from phenomenal experiences that process is taken to this unphenomenal or hyper- phenomenal self-explaining and self-subsistent substance, supporting all things without needing any support itself. Now, how does this hyperphenomenal \"substance,\" lodged in matter as a hard and qualityless core, help us to understand phenomenal reality? How can it ‘‘support’’ anything? And how can it be without supports? If the deity supports it, why should he support a support instead of directly supporting what needs his support?",
          "type": "quotation"
        },
        {
          "ref": "1914, Nikolaĭ Mikhaĭlovich Korkunov, William Granger Hastings, General Theory of Law, Boston Book Company, pages 319-320",
          "text": "But it is equally true that law has essentially a hyperphenomenal significance, inasmuch as it tends to institute an ethical order and attributes values, independent of physical actualization — without which it would not be law.",
          "type": "quotation"
        },
        {
          "ref": "1969, Giorgio Del Vecchio, Man and Nature: Selected Essays, Boston Book Company, page 8",
          "text": "In this sense we can say that all positive law—that is, all law exis ing in fact—is “natural”; by examining its determining factors and conditions we may come to understand its relative necessity and, as we say, explain it historically, but this does not imply any judgment concerning its intrinsic value as measured by the ideal standard of justice. This ideal is defined by the supreme law which corresponds to the spiritual essence of man, that is, to his hyperphenomenal nature. It is only in this latter sense that we can properly speak of natural law, as a paradigm and a rational criterion standing above positive law and enabling us to judge its value.",
          "type": "quotation"
        }
      ],
      "glosses": [
        "Above and beyond what is phenomenal; superphenomenal."
      ],
      "id": "en-hyperphenomenal-en-adj-6yRhwJPO",
      "links": [
        [
          "Above and beyond",
          "above and beyond"
        ],
        [
          "phenomenal",
          "phenomenal"
        ],
        [
          "superphenomenal",
          "superphenomenal"
        ]
      ],
      "raw_glosses": [
        "(rare) Above and beyond what is phenomenal; superphenomenal."
      ],
      "tags": [
        "rare"
      ]
    }
  ],
  "sounds": [
    {
      "ipa": "/ˈhaɪ.pə(ɹ)ˌfəˈnɒmɪnənəl/",
      "tags": [
        "Received-Pronunciation"
      ]
    },
    {
      "ipa": "/ˈhaɪ.pə(ɹ)ˌfəˈnɑməˌnɑnəl/",
      "tags": [
        "General-American"
      ]
    }
  ],
  "word": "hyperphenomenal"
}
{
  "etymology_templates": [
    {
      "args": {
        "1": "en",
        "2": "hyper",
        "3": "phenomenal"
      },
      "expansion": "hyper- + phenomenal",
      "name": "prefix"
    }
  ],
  "etymology_text": "hyper- + phenomenal",
  "forms": [
    {
      "form": "more hyperphenomenal",
      "tags": [
        "comparative"
      ]
    },
    {
      "form": "most hyperphenomenal",
      "tags": [
        "superlative"
      ]
    }
  ],
  "head_templates": [
    {
      "args": {},
      "expansion": "hyperphenomenal (comparative more hyperphenomenal, superlative most hyperphenomenal)",
      "name": "en-adj"
    }
  ],
  "hyphenation": [
    "hy‧per‧phe‧nom‧en‧al"
  ],
  "lang": "English",
  "lang_code": "en",
  "pos": "adj",
  "senses": [
    {
      "categories": [
        "English 7-syllable words",
        "English adjectives",
        "English entries with incorrect language header",
        "English lemmas",
        "English terms prefixed with hyper-",
        "English terms with IPA pronunciation",
        "English terms with quotations",
        "English terms with rare senses"
      ],
      "examples": [
        {
          "ref": "1882, Adam and Charles Black, Edinburgh, Encyclopedia Britannica & Dictionary - Ninth Edition (25 Volumes), Boston Book Company, page 8",
          "text": "In this sense we can say that all positive law—that is, all law exis ing in fact—is “natural”; by examining its determining factors and conditions we may come to understand its relative necessity and, as we say, explain it historically, but this does not imply any judgment concerning its intrinsic value as measured by the ideal standard of justice. This ideal is defined by the supreme law which corresponds to the spiritual essence of man, that is, to his hyperphenomenal nature. It is only in this latter sense that we can properly speak of natural law, as a paradigm and a rational criterion standing above positive law and enabling us to judge its value.",
          "type": "quotation"
        },
        {
          "ref": "1891, George Berkeley, Alexander Campbell Fraser, Selections from Berkeley: With an Introduction and Notes for the Use of Students in the Universities, page 37",
          "text": "He afterwards (§§ 3-24) goes on to argue that there can be nothing hyperphenomenal, or independent of a percipient mind, in the things of sense at least,—consistently with that faithful acceptance of experience, and rejection of empty words, on which he insists in the preceding Introduction.",
          "type": "quotation"
        },
        {
          "ref": "1897, Francis Turner Palgrave, Landscape in Poetry from Homer to Tennyson, Macmillan and Company, Limited, page 5",
          "text": "Compared with Nature in her infinite vastness, her infinite minuteness, our sphere is indeed limited. It is the surface of this little world—or, indeed only a small part of that surface—with sky and its earthbom features, and beyond, the heavenly bodies, as the fine old phrase names them, with which we are concerned; yet the aspects of Nature to man as he sees and loves and strives to render them in poetry, from the beginning we shall find have constantly either expressed or implied the sense of Divine causation or presence; and with this, that mysterious sense that we also are in some way one with what we see; that silent voices are speaking to us from land and sky, even that whatever we find of real existence, of the hyperphenomenal (if I may use the word) in ourselves, is immanent throughout the Cosmos. Or (to quote from an eminently thoughtful writer) man's personifications of natural scenery, we may say, are\" not the result of any mere ignorant \"fancy by which we project ourselves into external Nature, but \"evidently the result of an instinctive recognition of that\" special kind of agency which is, indeed, familiarly known to \"us as existing within ourselves, but which is also universally\" recognised and identified as existing outside of us and around \"us, on every side. It is a reflection of that infinite Reason,\" that Logos — of which we partake, and without which in \"Nature was not anything made that was made. All things, \"including ourselves, are full of it.\"",
          "type": "quotation"
        },
        {
          "ref": "1901, John James Tigert, Theism: A Survey of the Paths That Lead to God, Chiefly in the Light of History of Philosophy, Publishing House of the M.E. Church, South, Barbee & Smith, page 319",
          "text": "Mind you it is from phenomenal experiences that process is taken to this unphenomenal or hyper- phenomenal self-explaining and self-subsistent substance, supporting all things without needing any support itself. Now, how does this hyperphenomenal \"substance,\" lodged in matter as a hard and qualityless core, help us to understand phenomenal reality? How can it ‘‘support’’ anything? And how can it be without supports? If the deity supports it, why should he support a support instead of directly supporting what needs his support?",
          "type": "quotation"
        },
        {
          "ref": "1914, Nikolaĭ Mikhaĭlovich Korkunov, William Granger Hastings, General Theory of Law, Boston Book Company, pages 319-320",
          "text": "But it is equally true that law has essentially a hyperphenomenal significance, inasmuch as it tends to institute an ethical order and attributes values, independent of physical actualization — without which it would not be law.",
          "type": "quotation"
        },
        {
          "ref": "1969, Giorgio Del Vecchio, Man and Nature: Selected Essays, Boston Book Company, page 8",
          "text": "In this sense we can say that all positive law—that is, all law exis ing in fact—is “natural”; by examining its determining factors and conditions we may come to understand its relative necessity and, as we say, explain it historically, but this does not imply any judgment concerning its intrinsic value as measured by the ideal standard of justice. This ideal is defined by the supreme law which corresponds to the spiritual essence of man, that is, to his hyperphenomenal nature. It is only in this latter sense that we can properly speak of natural law, as a paradigm and a rational criterion standing above positive law and enabling us to judge its value.",
          "type": "quotation"
        }
      ],
      "glosses": [
        "Above and beyond what is phenomenal; superphenomenal."
      ],
      "links": [
        [
          "Above and beyond",
          "above and beyond"
        ],
        [
          "phenomenal",
          "phenomenal"
        ],
        [
          "superphenomenal",
          "superphenomenal"
        ]
      ],
      "raw_glosses": [
        "(rare) Above and beyond what is phenomenal; superphenomenal."
      ],
      "tags": [
        "rare"
      ]
    }
  ],
  "sounds": [
    {
      "ipa": "/ˈhaɪ.pə(ɹ)ˌfəˈnɒmɪnənəl/",
      "tags": [
        "Received-Pronunciation"
      ]
    },
    {
      "ipa": "/ˈhaɪ.pə(ɹ)ˌfəˈnɑməˌnɑnəl/",
      "tags": [
        "General-American"
      ]
    }
  ],
  "word": "hyperphenomenal"
}

This page is a part of the kaikki.org machine-readable English dictionary. This dictionary is based on structured data extracted on 2024-05-31 from the enwiktionary dump dated 2024-05-02 using wiktextract (91e95e7 and db5a844). The data shown on this site has been post-processed and various details (e.g., extra categories) removed, some information disambiguated, and additional data merged from other sources. See the raw data download page for the unprocessed wiktextract data.

If you use this data in academic research, please cite Tatu Ylonen: Wiktextract: Wiktionary as Machine-Readable Structured Data, Proceedings of the 13th Conference on Language Resources and Evaluation (LREC), pp. 1317-1325, Marseille, 20-25 June 2022. Linking to the relevant page(s) under https://kaikki.org would also be greatly appreciated.